The
pain that torture inflicts on its victims is instrumental. It is a means to an end. One way to conceive this end is from the
point of view of those who condone torture and justify it in the name of security. Such people ask us to believe that torturers
inflict severe pain on their victims in order to force them to divulge
information: precisely the sort of information that could save the lives of
those on whose behalf the torturer punishes his victims. Yet, the extent to which torture can help
secure this community from the dangers posed by the victim of torture and
his/her associates is questionable. As a
means of information gathering, torture is notoriously unreliable. Victims of torture may confess to whatever
the crimes –whether real or imagined—of which their torturers accuse them
simply out of a desire to make the pain that they are suffering cease and go
away. Torturers themselves are perfectly
aware of the unreliability of the information that they gather, which is why
they often must verify its accuracy. Regardless
of the outcome of this process of verification, torturers will always find reasons
to continue torturing their victims: if the information is accurate, they will torture
again with a renewed sense of confidence in their ability to gather useful
information; and if the information is inaccurate, torturers will punish their
victims with a renewed sense of urgency and vengeance. Given the unreliability
of torture as a means of information gathering and given also that, as a
consequence of this unreliability, torturers create their own reasons for
continuing to inflict pain on their victims, the claim that torture is
conducted in order to gather information seems rather specious.
When we reconsider
this claim from the perspective of the victims of torture, we can discern how torture
uses pain as a means to an altogether different end. From this perspective, torturers inflict
severe pain on their victims in order to get them to think, say, or do things
that violate who they have become thus far in life. That is: torturers torture in order to
humiliate their victims. The pain that
torturers inflict on their victims is meant to break down their victim’s loyalties
both to themselves and to their communities.
In other words, torturers inflict pain on their victims in an effort to
compel them to speak in other words.
From the point of view of the victims, these other words constitute a
language that contradicts their own language; they are words that only their
enemies would speak; so when the victims of torture are forced to speak this
language, they in effect are forced to speak the language of treason and
betrayal.
Victims of torture
are, in this sense, involuntary traitors.
They are people who have been forced to betray themselves and their own
people. The physical, mental, and
emotional pain that victims of torture are made to suffer is intended to push
them to the breaking point. What breaks at
this point is loyalty. Henceforth, the
victims of torture must live with the knowledge that they have become traitors:
enemies to their community; enemies to themselves. But it is not as though torture completely
breaks down all loyalty in those victims who it manages to turn into traitors. Involuntary traitors are left with one kind
of loyalty: loyalty to the trauma inflicted on them. They remember how, under the duress of
excruciating pain, they were forced to think, do, and say things of which they
will forever feel ashamed. The shame of
involuntary treason perpetuates the pain of torture by assuring that the
victims of torture replace their loyalty to self and community with a profound distrust
of their integrity as individuals and as members of a community. Convinced that they are untrustworthy, the
involuntary traitors that torture creates feel that they must bear the weight
of their shame alone.
Torture
aims to shame its victims and turn them into traitors because treason creates
rifts in communities; it fragments them; and breaks them down. Torture is a way to divide and conquer the
enemy. But torture is limited in its
ability to shatter the ties of loyalty that bind communities together. It can create involuntary traitors only on an
individual basis; it can humiliate its victims only one at a time. As a way around this limitation, regimes of
torture have often sought to make torture into a public spectacle: some
examples of this are the Autos de Fe celebrated by the Spanish Inquisition; the
witch-burnings in Salem, Massachusetts; or, more recently, the public
executions of heretics by the Taliban. When
torture is made the centerpiece of public spectacles such as these, it serves
as a threat to all who witness it. In
such instances, torture merges its power to utterly humiliate and shame
individuals with censorship’s power to humiliate and shame entire communities.
Censorship
generalizes the shame felt by the involuntary traitors that torture creates. It does this by threatening violence against and
imposing silence on those who might otherwise denounce the regime of torture. Those who obey the censor’s command to keep
silent internalize the threat of violence that underscores that command; thus,
they are made to share in the shame of involuntary treason that torture forces
on its victims. When the victims of
censorship obey the command to say not a disparaging word about torture, they
also become involuntary traitors; their silent complicity betrays the victims
of torture. This is why regimes of
torture often align themselves with regimes of censorship: torture creates
involuntary traitors who are, in turn, betrayed by the victims of censorship. Together, torture and censorship generate a
culture of treason.
Of
all the cruel and inhumane punishments that make up the torturer’s repertoire,
there is one in particular that demonstrates the extent to which torture and
censorship work in tandem to generate this culture of treason. This punishment is elinguation, or the
mangling, twisting, turning and eventual removal of the tongue. The tongue matters to torturers and censors
because it is the principle organ of speech, and of articulated positions of
either loyalty or betrayal. As such,
elinguation involves more than the literal removal of the tongue; it also
represents a metaphorical removal of language and community from the self. It both literally and metaphorically
displaces the victims of torture and censorship from their preferred
communities of speech.
It
is easy enough to understand how this punishment satisfies the desire of the
censor to impose a treasonous silence on his victims. It achieves in explicit terms what censorship
normally achieves only in implicit terms.
Less obvious is how this punishment satisfies the torturer’s desire to
force his victims to speak the language of betrayal. But it does so too in the sense that the
silence it imposes makes the victim of elinguation complicit with the language
that the torturer speaks. No longer able
to contradict his torturer, the victim of elinguation is ashamed to feel the
space that his tongue once occupied in his mouth filled with the filth of
censorship’s silence.
This
image of the tortured tongue is an apt metaphor for how the discussion on
torture has been carried out recently here in Washington, DC. Our tongues –although not literally removed
from our mouths, have been forcibly twisted and turned, such that we now speak
on torture in a language that contradicts the language in which we have
traditionally spoken of both torture and censorship. That language is intimately tied up with the
liberal tradition. It is the language in
which US constitutional law articulates prohibitions on torture and formulates
the equal rights of citizens; this language of enlightened liberalism is also the
language in which the Geneva Conventions and The United Nations Convention
against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment
articulate international prohibitions on torture and formulate the equal rights
of all humans.
At
issue in this language of enlightened liberalism is the idea that freedom must
be balanced against solidarity. This
balance is never easy to strike, and requires constant vigilance. Such is the case, in great measure, because
the language of liberalism does not conceive of either freedom or solidarity in
simple terms. Rather, it conceives them
each as a dynamic yet delicate balance between positive and negative
aspects. As concerns freedom, our
positive freedom to realize ourselves and our life projects is limited
negatively by other people’s freedom from coercion. As such, we are generally prepared to accept our
freedom from coercion as a necessary limit that is imposed on our freedom to do
with our lives as we please. Likewise,
as concerns solidarity, our right to associate with others positively on the
basis of shared characteristics, values, or interests is limited negatively by
other people’s right to not have such associations forced on them. For this reason, we are generally willing to accept
the idea that our common humanity should act as a negative limit on the
prerogatives of our positive circles of solidarity.
When
it is applied to questions of torture and censorship, the inherent logic of
this language establishes an analogy where Torture: Solidarity :: Censorship:
Freedom. According to this reasoning, no
positively defined circle of solidarity (such as a tribe, an ethnic or
religious community, or a nation) can trump the negative solidarity that is
constructed on the basis of all of us having nothing in common aside from the
fact that we are members of the same species.
This negative solidarity imposes a limit on freedom by prohibiting
torture as a violation of our human dignity.
As concerns the positive solidarity that censorship constructs by
imposing silence, the logic of enlightened liberalism suggests that it is
limited by our freedom from coercion.
This negative freedom imposes a limit on solidarity by prohibiting
censorship, which is conceived as a violation of our freedom to grow into
full-fledged individuals who think and speak for themselves.
The Bybee and
Gonzales memos, which the Bush administration prepared in 2002 in anticipation
of the US invasion of Iraq, turned this logic on its head. The new Bush-speak on torture inverted the
terms of enlightened liberalism’s prohibition analogy, replacing the negative
relationships between torture and solidarity on the one hand and censorship and
freedom on the other with positive ones.
As opposed to Torture: Solidarity :: Censorship : Freedom, the new
discourse on torture proposed that Torture: Freedom :: Censorship: Solidarity. According to this logic, torturers are the
ultimate expression of freedom; and censors are the ultimate creators of
solidarity. The positive freedom enjoyed
by torturers knows no limits; it is neither limited by the victim’s negative
freedom from coercion nor by the negative solidarity that ties torturers to
their victims insofar as they are both human beings. Much the same can be said about the censors
who this new Bush-speak on torture empower.
The positive solidarity that these censors construct by imposing silence
knows no limits; it is neither limited by the negative solidarity of those with
whom the censors have nothing in common except their humanity, nor is it
limited by the negative liberty from coercion of the victims of
censorship. Failing to acknowledge any
of these limits, the positive solidarity that these censors create is as
narcissistic as it is jingoistic.
Indeed, the trouble with this overly-positive notion of solidarity is
that it has led some Americans to embrace a sense of patriotism that would
require all Americans to identify positively with torturers, as opposed to
identifying at least negatively with their victims.
I trust my
comments have made clear the extent to which this new language on torture, and
the censorship that accompanies it, openly contradict the traditional language
of enlightened liberalism on which our and all other modern democracies are
based. Insofar as we acquiesce to use
this new language or fail to denounce the silences it imposes, we run the risk
of becoming involuntary traitors and sharing in the shame that now permanently
marks the lives of those “enemy combatants” who have been tortured on our
behalf, ostensibly in order to secure our freedom and affirm our solidarity.
The outcome of the
recent Presidential election here in the US suggests that a majority of the
American public has now decided to reject the new language on torture that was
devised in secretive meetings and became policy without even the slightest
public debate. Perhaps this majority favors
a return to the more traditional language of enlightened liberalism. I hope they do not. For if the Bybee and Gonzalez memos prove
anything, it is that the language in which we have traditionally formulated our
prohibitions on torture is too weak; the negative limits we have traditionally
imposed on freedom and solidarity have proved to be malleable, twistable, and
torturous. We do need stronger language
in which to prohibit torture and censorship while at the same time affirming
our solidarity as a species. My hope,
although it is not terribly audacious, is that this symposium today serves as a
first step in that direction.
No comments:
Post a Comment